Psychotherapy Integration PapersInfluential Readings
on Psychotherapy Integration
|
||||||||
Editor's note. This article was published in the Journal of
European Psychoanalysis, 12-13, 2001. It is a
commentary on Lawrence Friedman's "Ferrum, ignis,
and medicina: return to the crucible". Journal of the
American Psychoanalytic Association, 1997, 45,
21-37. It is followed by a rejoinder
by Friedman. The logic of the therapeutic relationship
Tullio Carere-Comes
SummaryFriedman
pointed out that "Freud did not design a treatment: he
discovered one". It means that psychoanalytic therapy is
a robust phenomenon, endowed with an inner logic or an
essential structure of its own. Two elements of this
structure are highlighted by Friedman: the "hunt for
objective truth" and the "adversarial attitude". The
Author builds on this basic core to extend it in two
directions. Firstly, he contends that the essential
structure pointed to by Friedman is not a property of
psychoanalytic therapy alone, but is shared by any
genuine psychotherapy, ie any treatment that does not
dissociate the tactical objective of symptom relief from
the strategical objective of personal formation.
Secondly, he locates the two Friedman's factors on the
two orthogonal axes—the uncovering and the remaking
line—that define the field of psychotherapy. On these
axes, connecting each two cardinal therapeutic
positions, the two Friedman's factors are doubled to
four, ie two couples of opposite therapeutic factors.
This doubling, which transforms Friedman's linear logic
into a dialectical one, is deemed necessary to overcome
the unilaterality of the former. In a dialectical
approach truth is not just hunted or conquered, it is
also received or generated; and the resistances are met
with an adversarial, as much as with a reassuring and
validating attitude. A balance is to be struck moment by
moment between hunting and receiving, as between
wrestling and reassuring, as a function of the demands
of the process. 1. "Freud did not design a treatment: he
discovered one". If it were not so, as Friedman points out,
therapy would be an arbitrary venture: If I am wrong in
my assumption—if treatment is just the application to
patients of whatever analytic theory happens to be
knocking around at the moment—then my method is
pointless. Analytic psychotherapy—and I would add
psychotherapy tout court—is not in its essence a
construction. It is something that happens and is
observable in the treatment setting: It is a robust
phenomenon. This is equivalent to say that the
treatment has an inner logic
of its own, which determines the observable structure.
One can even start from hypnosis, as Freud himself
did. But if one is guided by the logic of the process,
and not by the wish to get at something (like
repressed memories, catharsis, or whatever), the
relationship reveals an essential structure, that is a
set of properties that any genuinely therapeutic
relationship must feature. Two points of this
structure are highlighted by Friedman: the hunt for
objective truth and the adversarial
attitude.
One can dispute whether the elements of the
process being hypothesized by Friedman are the only
elements, or whether they are the most basic among
others. One can point out a contradiction between the
willingness to be guided by the logic of the process
and the decision to take into account, in the study of
its components, only "Anglo-American, Freudian
analysis". One can object that every therapy, inasmuch
as it is a cultural product, is also a
construction depending on some premises and
worldviews. All this, however, does not detract from
the substance of Friedman's observation. In fact, if
an essential core, or an invariant structure, did not
exist in every genuine psychoanalytic or
psychotherapeutic relationship, all discourse on
psychoanalysis or psychotherapy would fall into
meaninglessness for lack of a real referent, and the
psychoanalytic/psychotherapeutic theories could not be
distinguished from the myriad of cults competing on
the market for the care of the souls. Quite often, in the attempt to define this essential core or structure, the term "psychoanalysis" is employed for the genuine therapy, while the term "psychotherapy" is applied to a generic container for all merely symptomatic, suggestive or manipulative practices. This distinction echoes of course the one made by Freud, between the gold of psychoanalysis and the copper of suggestion. The same terminological distinction is also used in the attempt to separate "psychoanalysis" as a search for truth or a way of personal liberation from "psychotherapy" as a technical-scientific profession similar to medical practice. In both cases the distinction seems inadequate. It is true that symptomatic, suggestive and manipulative practices, as all sorts of "short term therapies", do exist: but in all these cases it seems more appropriate to speak of "bad" psychotherapy. Even inside the medical paradigm a therapy that only aims to eliminate the symptoms is just a symptomatic therapy, while a good medical therapy acts as much as possible on the cause of the illness. Besides, the statement that psychoanalysis, unlike psychotherapy, can bring about a radical transformation, has never been convincingly demonstrated and still remains today a mere petitio principii.One can agree with Contardi when he says a propos of psychoanalysis that "therapy does not occur without subjective formation and this proceeds producing therapeutic effects"—save that this can be said of any good psychotherapy, not just of psychoanalysis. Indeed no psychotherapy can be deemed good, if the tactical objective of symptom relief is set apart from the strategical objective of personal formation or growth. The articulation between tactical and strategical objectives, on the other hand, cannot follow a fixed scheme. Sometimes the former, other times the latter, are at the forefront. A symptom-centered work can bring about an important personal transformation, just as the work on deep conflicts can cause the resolution of a symptom. However, it is the more likely that such things happen, the more the other side of the coin, even if implicit, is kept in mind. It very often happens instead that the more tactically oriented treatments (the "psychotherapies") do not pay enough attention to the strategy, while those more strategically oriented (the "psychoanalyses") neglect the tactics, ie the treatment of the symptoms with apt techniques. They both do a bad service to their patients, when the protection of the identity of the therapist is privileged to the detriment of the patient's needs. When on the contrary the attention to these needs prevails, the psychoanalyst becomes a psychotherapist (one who does not disdain the use of many cognitive, behavioral, and experiential techniques), and the psychotherapist becomes a psychoanalyst (inasmuch as they carry out an ongoing monitoring of the experience of the relationship on both sides—or, if one prefers, they analyse the transference and the countertransference). With the consequence that the difference between the two becomes almost irrelevant. As a consequence, the words "psychoanalysis" and "psychotherapy" can be used as synonyms in most cases. Instead of looking after uncertain and improbable distinctions, it could be more useful to define what is essential and structural in any genuine therapeutic relationship, whatever one prefers to call it. With this aim, the two basic attitudes indicated by Friedman seem to be a good point of departure. Here is the first: The analyst could
press his own case without entreating the patient and
without manipulating the patient because the patient's
ultimate response was guaranteed,
theoretically, by a third presence—objective truth,
truth undistorted by the analyst's and patient's
preconceptions and wishful thinking. These words define the basic attitude not
just of psychoanalysis, but of every relational
therapy, because the incapacity or unavailability to
neutralize one's personal or school preconceptions is
the hallmark feature of all practices of manipulation
or indoctrination. It is hardly questionable that the
suspension of all analyst's and patient's
preconceptions is the very foundation of any genuine
psychotherapy, whereas on the attribute objective for
the substantive truth
one cannot be equally sure. Benvenuto has for instance
observed: hermenutic
criticism has reminded us modern folk, insofar as we
are all (fatally) "enlightened", a bitter truth: that
it is impossible to know something without
interpreting, and that it is impossible to be
definitively "objective". Everyone interprets on the base of one's
personal or school myths. The crisis of the Freudian
interpretation (no longer revealing an objective
truth, but just a myth among many) is, however,
healthy, "insofar as it reduces a chronic tendency in
much of psychoanalysis towards interpretive
omnipotence". This crisis means that we are now
aware that one can never fully bracket out the myths
(prejudgements, preconceptions) that are at the root
of one's interpretations. This crisis can pave the way
to positions of relativism or radical constructivism,
where everyone is wrapped in one's own myth (or one's
own theory), and can communicate only with those who
share the same premises. Truth disappears from this
horizon, being "functionality" the only boundary left
against chaos.
Once the illusion that interpretation reveals
objective facts has been abandoned, what will save us
from nihilism, dangerously courted by Nietzsche
("facts don't exist, only interpretations do")? How is
it possible to distance oneself from the old naive,
dogmatic certainties, without falling into the
opposite extreme of postmodern constructionism; how
can one avoid the trap, in other words, of the false
alternative between scientism and skepticism? If the
identification of reality and objectivity is the trap,
the way out will be the separation of these two
notions, for reality to be traced back to the
ontological or noumenical foundation that is lost in
any objectivation.
Only what is is real:
the ontological referent, in itself unknowable, of
every knowledge . Every knowledge (K) is a transformation
of the thing in itself (O). When we try to know a
thing, we unavoidably transform it. What we know is
the result of that transformation, not the thing as it
is in itself, independent of our action. But the
transformation can both reveal and conceal the thing.
What shall we know then of its truth? We can first of
all apply the classic criterium of conformity (adequatio rei et
intellectus): the validity of a knowledge
depends on its adequacy to the ontological referent.
This criterium of course is not usable in the
constructivist perspective, from which the ontological
referent has disappeared. If we recover it—as we must
do if we want to get rid of the dilemma between
scientism and skepticism—we also recover the criterium
of conformity, but its application requires the
clarification of some premises.
To begin with, as hermeneutic criticism has
reminded us of the impossibility of being definitively
objective, we have to give up the simple and naive
objectivity of scientism, but this does not sanction
the denial of any space and value to the object and to
the scientific activity that produces it. As biology
allows us to know some aspects of the living being,
those aspects that the theoretical-technical apparatus
of the biologist cuts out from the reality of the
living world (ontological referent), which is
incommensurably vaster than the cut out part
(objective knowledge), so psychology allows us to know
what its instruments cut out from the reality of the
psychic world, this too incommensurably vaster than
the part that has been cut out. Biology and psychology
are nothing but theoretical-technical activities, and
the objects produced by them. If the procedures are
correct, the objects that are the result of these
procedures are adequate
to the referent, ie they allow us to know some
partial aspects of it. But only the correspondance to
the referent, established by repeated and controlled
comparison with the investigated reality, will allow
us to ascertain the quality and the measure of such
adequacy.
Being the result of the theoretical-technical
procedures applied, the object is always an
interpretation of the subject. On the other hand, as
the procedures are bound to the ontological referent,
the result will not be arbitrary, but will describe
the aspect of reality that is defined by the selected
criteria—the more rigorously the procedure has been
applied, the more faithfully this aspect of reality is
described. The recovery of the ontological referent
therefore permits us to overcome the distinction
between hermeneutics and science, or between natural
and human sciences, whose artificiality has been
pointed out by Holt. In this sense
psychoanalysis—interpretive discipline par
excellence—is a science in its own right, provided
that it rigorously defines its theoretical and
technical apparatus. The same is true for every form
of psychotherapy.
If, on the one hand, the link to the
ontological referent allows us to grant a status of
objectivity to the interpretive procedures, this on
the other hand is no bullwark against the unlimited
multiplication of perspectives, leading to the
proliferation of schools and psychotherapeutic
languages. Every paradigm is entitled to revenge its
own scientific foundation, though remaining
incomparable and incompatible with the others. Thanks
to the specificity and originality of its means, it is as
though every approach highlighted a particular sector
of the "thing" (or of the therapeutic field),
providing us with a valid and objective knowledge of
that sector, though incomparable with the others. As a
matter of fact the very loyalty to a given paradigm
warrants on one hand the rigor of the procedure, while
on the other it insulates the sector defined by it
from all the others, defined by rival paradigms.
If the pluralism resulting from the
multiplication of perspectives can be welcomed as a
step forward in respect to the monolithic ideologies,
it is not an acceptable outcome for psychotherapy. The
surrender to the pulverization of schools and methods
would mean indeed the resignation to the impossibility
for the therapist to transcend the theoretical frame
that orders his or her world, thus sanctioning the
impossibility of communication among adherents to
different paradigms, and the definitive illusoriness
of a genuine
listening. Such a "postmodern" outcome could be
accepted if only aesthetical values were at stake,
which is not the case in psychotherapy—a discipline
that, as was pointed out above, is different from
indoctrinating or manipulative practices inasmuch as
it is systematically and constantly grounded on the
capacity and will to neutralize all personal and
scholastic preconceptions and wishful thinking.
We started with the observation that the corner
stone of psychotherapy—neutrality—is contradicted by
the hermeneutic criticism that "it is impossible to
know anything without interpreting". The retrieval of
the ontological referent allowed us to return a
relative validity to the objectivity of
interpretation, but only inside a given paradigm,
whereas the choice of the latter remains completely up
to subjective preference—it is out of the question
that one could ever "objectively" demonstrate the
superiority of, say, a cognitive paradigm over a
Lacanian one. If this were the point of arrival of our
investigation, we would face here an insuperable
contradiction between the basic assumption of genuine
psychotherapy and hermeneutical critique, inasmuch as
what the former demands the latter denies. Should we
then give up one or the other?
Many
conflicts that seem insuperable as long as they are
addressed from the standpoint of linear logic, are no
more so in a dialectical perspective. If we recognize
the value of either enunciated principle, it will
suffice to renounce the pretence for the one or the
other to be unilaterally valid, to see that the
contradiction relates to the two terms of a
dialectical polarity. The first step has been done—the
pretence of a perfect neutrality, if we ever harbored
it, was swept away by hermeneutic criticism. The
second step must be in the opposite direction.
Hermeneutic criticism, which left to itself bolsters
the anarchic proliferation of interpretations, must in
turn be moderated by the call of neutrality, in search
of the balance without which the therapeutic operation
is unconceivable. 2. The dialectic
of interpretation and neutralization has been
described, albeit in different words (assimilation and
accommodation), by Piaget. In the course of normal
development the child firstly tries to assimilate all
new data to her available cognitive schemata, ie she
interprets them in the light of preexisting models,
myths or theories. Piagetian assimilation
substantially corresponds to hermeneutic interpretance,
an ongoing, structural attitude of the human being.
However, the healthy child does more than
assimilation. Facing contradiction, she does not
insist on trying to force reality into her schemata,
but she finally suspends those schemata, stepping back
and letting the new data enter into her horizon. In so
doing, the child does not interpret, but sees
something new, thanks to the suspension of the
assimilative attitude. Instead of assimilating the
data to her schemata, she accommodates her perceptive
apparatus to the reality in front of her. The child's
accommodation is the first embryo of phenomenology's epoché,
in which the bracketing of expectations and
preconceptions permits her to receive what appears in
that opening. And it is only for this systematic
neutralization that her schemata are modified and
enriched.
The same dialectical movement is found in the
hermeneutic circle. Any interpretation starts with a
precognition, as Heidegger pointed up. Reevaluating
prejudgment as a source of understanding, and denying
the possibility of a neutral interpretation, Heidegger
lucidly illustrated the general condition of
interpretation. In this emphasis of understanding
through interpretation, however, one intuits the wish
of the disciple to emancipate from his master Husserl,
who in an equally unilateral way had insisted on
neutrality. More balanced than either one of these is
Freud's position, which is "Heideggerian" in the
prescription of the Oedypal mythology as the base for
the production of meaning in the analytic narratives,
and "Husserlian" when he suggests to proceed free of
expectations, facing whatever happens in an
open-minded way and without preconceptions.
The hermeneutic circle can function in the mode
of vicious or
virtuous circle.
In the former the theory or myth is the same at the
departure and at the end of a movement in which the
conclusions regularly confirm the premises. It is the
way of all orthodoxy, and the reason for the well
known—and for this reason just—exclusion by Popper of
psychoanalysis from the scientific field. In the
virtuous circle the implicit presuppositions are
firstly employed for a preliminary understanding of
the data, and then suspended for a fuller
understanding, inclusive of whatever the initial
presuppositions could not grasp. The figure of the
circle is apt to describe a movement in which the
point of arrival (the fuller understanding) is brought
to bear onto the point of departure, which allows for
the theory to be constantly modified and enriched.
There exists one more possibility, a third and
more insidious mode of hermeneutic circle which is
neither openly vicious, nor clearly virtuous. It
happens when the initial assumption is suspended as a
function of the expectations of the other. What is
lacking here is a true neutralization. The subject
does not suspend his or her assumptions in the name of
truth, but just comes to terms with, or negotiates a
solution acceptable to both parties. As the mediation
is not in the name of truth but in that of compromise,
the process leads to a reciprocal adaptation which is
not in the maturative direction, but in that of a
false self à
deux. In the relationship between a couple,
between the leader and his followers, or even between
analyst and analysand, each party tends to consciously
or unconsciously adapt to the knowledge of the other
(theories, models, phantasies). It is necessary to
distinguish this pseudo adaptation—in fact, a
reciprocal collusive manipulation—from a true
adaptation to reality. The true accommodation is not a
negotiation of knowledge, but the correction of a
preexisting schema which follows the suspension of all
knowledge: the jump into the void that Bion pointed to
with the formula Faith in O,
which means entrusting oneself to the unknowable
origin of all knowledge. I will try now to show the dialectic of the hermeneutic circle as it unfolds in the writings of Benvenuto and Napolitani. Benvenuto holds a prudently intermediate position between those who exceed either in a scientific or in a hermeneutic sense, ie on the side of the object or on that of the subject. On the one side one "aims for the objectivity of something elementary, for a primary cause which, in so far as cause, has no meaning... This love for the term 'elementary' is always the indicator of a reductionist attitude: the objectivist runs from the complex (the olon), and seeks peace or a safe haven in the elementary". On the other side, "the resignation of analysis to an hermeneutic game—ie to elaborate interpretations that only History will be able to judge—is a sign of its crisis... Those who discredit psychoanalysis think in fact that it deals only with interpretations, and never really with something real—that the analyst is not a witness to some thing (das Ding) that the subject discovers, but a manipulator of the subject's beliefs". In the search for a real that is not reduced
to an elementary, meaningless objectivity, nor
dissolved in an endless flight of interpretations of
interpretations, Benvenuto finds a track in the
"affect of truth" that is "certainly the result of the
analyst's likely historical-hermeneutic
re-constructions which reveal the subject's
interpretive defense: but on the horizon, this affect
of truth points out to the subject—finally perceiving
herself as something other than what she believed
herself to be—the possibility of interpreting herself
otherwise, and opening herself to that otherness that
dislodges her". The real is therefore defined by
contrast to the imaginary: It is other than what the
subject imagines to be, it is what she finds before
herself—what she has to come to terms with—when she
uncovers the self deception in which she had taken
refuge or had been trapped. The affect of truth is the
liberating feeling which signals the exposure of the
self deception, and at the same time points up to the
reality that the deception concealed. The analyst
pushes the subject to become permeable to an otherness
that Benvenuto exemplifies as "biological drive,
trauma, demands and interpretations from without": an
otherness that has the quality of an inevitable given,
or a given that is only avoidable at the price of a
self segregation into a neurosis. However, according to Diego Napolitani , "every 'discovered truth' is a deceit, ie a fanciful approximation to 'how things really are'". If "there is no objective reality, no encounter with the world, which is not a hybrid, that is the result of a violence (ubris) of individual preconception on perceived data", then even what Benvenuto identifies as "real" (drives, traumas, demands from the outside world) can be nothing but the product of the same violence that constantly tries to pass off its own constructions as real. Does it mean that there is no way out of one's epistemological cages or shells? One way does exist, says Napolitani, and it consists in recovering "the naked gaze of the child", that is "a way of seeing which does not presuppose a single aim, therefore surprises, open to comprehension and uninterested in the explanation, not caught up with the shapes on our side of the horizon, because it sees that which is beyond sensible limits. The gaze of the mystic, of the poet". But what is the relation between the interpretive violence and the naked gaze? Violence belongs to the Freudian unconscious, meant as "the space of the repressed, the 'totally already known' which makes itself present, beyond a critical awareness, as an a priori law, the law of the defunct, the moral conscience". If experience is governed by the law of the defunct, of the already known, its categories will be confirmed in an endless repetition. But if the defunct is evoked, as in the old psychagogical ceremonies, "in order to conclude the time of his death... his heir has the possibility of not remaining confused with him, of taking that reflective, critical, aesthetic distance in which he can minimally affirm his originality... originality does not imply the impossible being beyond one's own history, but a singular way of taking up once more one's own history (one's own origins) not to repeat it, but to transform it". The naked gaze corresponds then to "the negative capacity already formulated by Keats and then by Bion. It is the capacity to tolerate change and it is founded on the shifting of the existential center of gravity towards the future and becoming. The mind which does not reject its own conception has faith... in its ability to find itself once more, grown in its own continuity, beyond change". This faith allows the jump into the void, the abandonment of the certainty of the already known (though unconscious), to entrust oneself to the generative matrix (the unknown). Benvenuto and Napolitani have a point in common, but then their ways diverge. This base is also common to all those, like Jacques-Alain Miller and Jean Laplanche, for whom "the interpretation is above all that of the unconscious, in the sense of the subjective genitive: it is the unconscious that interprets". The interpretation is seen as a primarily defensive operation, which protects from something that is pointed out as the true, the real, the unknown, the thing-in-itself. The primary objective of psychoanalysis therefore is to unmask this operation, uncovering the interpretations to which the identity of the subject has remained stuck, to bring her back to whatever she has repressed by means of those interpretations. How is it possible that from this common ground one arrives to divergent or seemingly opposite conclusions, as in the case of Benvenuto and Napolitani? My answer is that the opposition is only apparent, if one considers that Benvenuto and Napolitani have highlighted respectively the two terms of a dialectical polarity, the one that Bion refers to with the letters K and O, the actual and the potential, the phenomenon and the noumenon. In the K vertex the analyst confronts the subject with those real data that are like unavoidable stumbling blocks on her existential path. Heavy data, biological, biographical, or environmental, with which one has to come to terms, if one does not want to remain stuck to them. There is a "real in K" which is made up of these concretions, ie of the material, familiar, historical, social conditions of the existence of the subject. The human being, thanks to his "neothenic" unachievement, is different from any other animal for his extraordinary capability of ongoing transformation of the conditions of his existence, in which he breaks the material or epistemological shells that imprison him, to reconceive and rebirth himself in ever new and unforeseeable forms. In the O vertex of the therapy field, the analyst and her patient, "bound by a common evocation of their own 'deceased' (of their own history, ideology, common sense, theories, psychoanalytical knowledge)" continuously dissolve and recreate the forms of their existence. 3. We have passed from Friedman's "hunt for
objective truth" to the set of operations on the line
connecting the O and K vertex of the therapeutic
field. An initial concept of objectivity has been
examined: the one that exists inside a given paradigm,
the object being inseparable from the
theoretical-technical procedures that produce it.
Because genuine (non manipulative) psychotherapy
happens only insofar as all pretence of imposing one's
own personal or scholastic paradigm is suspended—the
space of therapeutic dialogue opens thanks to this
suspension—the criterion of objectivity, though not
alien to the truths that are discovered in
psychotherapy, meets here with a problematic
application. In the first place the
self-interpretations in which the identity of the
subject has remained trapped must be brought to
light, furthering the encounter with the real that
they screened. One is guided, in this part of the
work, by the "affect of truth" (as Benvenuto
conveniently calls it), more than by the procedures
commmonly employed when the aim is to establish the
objectivity of a proposition. But once we find
ourselves in the face of that real that the alienating
interpretations concealed, the question of its
objectivity appears in a new form.
It is a question that we do not have to face,
if we stick to the Lacanian definition according to
which "le
réel est l'impossible". Indeed, if the
real that one finally encounters is nothing but the
impossibility of the desire (of true love, of
immortality…), then the surrender to this
impossibility is the price to pay to stop the endless
flight into neurotic interpretance. But this would be
an ethical task, not a scientific venture. If then,
beyond a stoical acceptance of the unavoidable, we
make out the possibility of getting rid of our
interpretive cages, towards a reinterpretation of
existence that is no more neurotic, but creative and
regenerative, the space that opens wide in front of us
is that of the art of living, which has little or
nothing to do with science. Psychotherapy is certainly
a complex operation, inseparable from an ethical and
philosophical committment. What, in its scope, could
still claim a scientific foundation?
If such a foundation is indeed to be claimed,
it will no longer suffice that a school of
psychoanalysis or psychotherapy defines its
theoretical-technical apparatus, self-limiting its own
pretence of objectivity to the objects that this
apparatus cuts out in the real. Even if in so doing a
partial aspect of the thing is described, the
self-referential withdrawal on one's own objects
(practice, rites, language) observable in most
existing schools is incompatible with the minimal
demands of the scientific discourse. This in fact
requires that instead of the necessary comparison
between different and competing hypotheses being used
as a key for identifying followers, forwarding careers
and marginalizing heretics (as happens nowadays), any
theoretical assumption be viewed as an hypothesis to
be verified or falsified in the ongoing public
confrontation with experience. This confrontation is
not possible if the object under investigation is
generated by the theory through which it is
investigated (in which case self-referentiality is
unavoidable), but only if the real
referent to which all theories are bound is neutral
in respect to the theories themselves—if it is
"transtheoretical" or "metatheoretical".
One can deny the very existence of such a
theoretically neutral referent, as happens with a
postmodern, radically constructivist perspective. If
it were true, however, that everyone is unredeemably
closed up in one's own theoretical paradigm, not only
would any dialogue among adherents to different
paradigms be impossible, but psychotherapy itself
would be impossible. Genuine psychotherapy is grounded
on dialogue,
and dialogue is the type of communication in which the
presuppositions of those who are engaged in it are as
neutralized as necessary to have the logos of the
relationship emerge. The assertion of the existence of
a logos (a logic, a ratio, an order) in things is
certainly a matter of faith, but it is the faith on
which every scientific venture is grounded. In
particular, it is not possible to think of
psychotherapy as a scientifically based operation
outside the assumption that psychotherapy is governed
by an inner logic of its own, in spite of the
virtually unlimited variety of techniques and the
unforeseeable singularity of every encounter. In other
words, the arbitrariness of theoretical and technical
options can be avoided if psychotherapy is anchored to
a structure of its own, ie to a set of invariants,
regularities or recurrent configurations that
structure any psychotherapeutic relationship,
independently of the school of the therapist and the
preferences of both therapist and patient. The paradox
of the Dodo
verdict—"all have won, all deserve a prize", the
outcome equivalence of the different therapeutic
methods—seems to demonstrate that psychotherapy works,
but for reasons that are only weakly connected to the
technical choices of the therapist. It works because
every therapist is persuaded by the inner logic of the
relationship to respond to the real needs that are in
play in every therapeutic relationship, whether or not
they are foreseen by his or her school. With this we
return to Friedman's observation from which we
started: therapy,
in its essential features, is not an invention, but
a discovery.
What do we discover? We discover firstly
that the therapy relationship takes the form of an
uncovering work. There is a wide convergence to the
acknowledgement that a basic feature of every therapy
consists in unearthing the interpretations that the
subject has given of themselves, their world and their
history, and in which they have remained entangled,
whatever the form of their interpretations:
unconscious phantasies, cognitive schematas, emotional
schemes, relational scripts. Though anachronistic and
disadvantageous, the subject, as a rule, defends them
stubbornly, and vigorously resists any attempt to
modify them. They are defended because of their
protective function in respect to something which,
right or wrong, one is afraid to face—old wounds that
still hurt, unsatisfied needs, unresolved conflicts,
existential decisions in present life. The "hunt for
objective truth"—Friedman's first factor—clearly
refers to the inescapable necessity for any therapy to
unmask the mental constructions that separate the
subject from the reality that is their own.
The dimension of discovery, however, cannot be
entirely reduced to a "hunt for objective truth"—this
would throw a vaguely persecutory shade on the
relationship. It is not just about uncovering the
"real" that the subject shuns, but also the
unexpressed "potential" which can be drawn upon to
generate new forms of existence. Therapists who
systematically faced their patients with the real they
escape, without knowing at the same time how to awaken
the trust in the healing and regenerative power upon
which to draw to transform the real they fear, would
probably drive their patients and themselves into a
blind alley. The uncovering line of the therapy field
can therefore be represented as an axis connecting the
K and O poles of the real and the potential, of the
known and the unknown, or of the phenomenon and the
noumenon. This is the main axis of any genuine
therapy, independently of the persuasion of the
therapist.
Therapy, on the other hand, is not just a
matter of uncovering. It is an uncovering operation
only when, and to the extent to which, a good enough working alliance
has been established. But a working alliance firstly
has to be created, and secondly has to be sustained.
To create and to sustain a working alliance is one
thing, to work in the space opened by a working
alliance is another thing. These two things can be
seen as the two levels or axes of the therapy field.
At this more basic level we find the second Friedman's
therapeutic factor: the adversarial
attitude, meaning the fight against the
resistance, ie the unwillingness to face whatever is
to be faced. Its necessity derives from the rebellion
of the infantile mind to whatever challenges the
omnipotence of the desire. This factor was explicit in
Freud, when he wrote that the patient suffers not
because he does not know, but because he does not want
to know. The problem, in Freud's view, is not resolved
by communicating to a person what he or she does not
know, but fighting his or her inner
resistances. The first duty of the therapist,
therefore, is not the uncovering of what is concealed,
but the fight against the resistance, in Freud's
words, or the adversarial attitude, in Friedman's.
This concept might be implicit in that of the "hunt
for the objective truth", because the hunter knows
that the prey will do its best to avoid capture.
However, as long as the emphasis is on objective
truth, the basic attitude is that of the scientist,
who investigates with as neutral as possible a frame
of mind, whereas the emphasis on resistance implies a
shift from neutrality to a deliberately adversarial
involvement: What I call
adversarialness, and what Freud described in similar
idiom, refers to the way the analyst sets his face
against appeals by the patient, denies bids for
validation and reassurance, sternly summons what is
most reluctant…. This is a very good point. Surely, on many occasions
a therapist cannot help but present a stern face and
deny bids for validation and reassurance. But is this
the only face of a therapist? Are there no other occasions,
in which the offer of validation and reassurance is in
order? To answer this question, we shoud keep in mind
Friedman's warning: to decide what belongs or does not
belong to psychoanalysis (or, for that matter,
psychotherapy), we should not rely on theory—on any
theory whatsoever. Ie, we cannot answer that
reassurance is permitted or forbidden, just because
our theory foresees or does not foresee it. If we did
so, the result would not be analysis or therapy, but scholastic
(stereotyped) analysis or therapy. It is not one
school's theory that we must interrogate for such an
answer, but the inner
logic of the psychoanalytic (or
psychotherapeutic) relationship. And the inner logic
tells us what more and more psychoanalysts realize: insight is not
enough. Why is insight not enough? Because if it
were enough, the analyst would not need move from the
neutral position of the scientist in the first place,
which is something they do everytime they take the
adversarial attitude—which in turn they must do to
fight the inner resistances. By the same token, a
parent puts on a stern face when a child tries to shun
something unpleasant that is beneficial for them.
Indeed, the adversarial attitude is nothing but the
basic parental attitude of confronting
the child with whatever they are trying to escape. On
the other hand, this does not go without the polarly
opposite parental attitude of validating and
reassuring. These two attitudes make up another basic
dialectic, between the paternal-confronting
and the maternal-reassuring
vertices[1]
of the therapy field. 4. When someone is fully motivated to know and
face whatever is there to be known and faced, there is
no need for an adversarial attitude, just as when a
person is secure of his or her right to exist and to
be whatever he or she is, there is no need for a
reassuring attitude. There can be moments or whole
sessions in which the therapist can remain at least
relatively neutral, because the whole work takes place
on the uncovering line. But there can hardly exist a
therapy in which the therapist will not have to shift
from time to time to the remaking or
reparenting line, the one connecting the maternal and
the paternal vertices of the field. The two Friedman's
factors are representative of both lines, but with a
distinct male-analytic prevalence. If we correct this
bias including the female-synthetic side of the whole,
what we get is two couples of cardinal factors (O-K,
M-P) and two orthogonal axes (remaking and uncovering)
which describe the field of therapy. Friedman's
two-factor model is enlarged to a four-factor one that
accounts for virtually all therapeutic interactions.
The widening of the scope is required by the
dialectics of the interaction. Too much emphasis on
the K vertex, not balanced by the spontaneous and
generative interventions of the O vertex, risks giving
the relationship an epistemophilic, tendentially
obsessive character, which in turn would bolster
iatrogenic resistances. If therapy is too much of a hunt, and too
little a play, it is all too easy for the patient to
feel hunted,
especially when one is so predisposed—in which case
the predisposition would be confirmed. Similarly, if
the therapist's attitude is too adversarial, and not
reassuring enough—if the therapist's face is too
stern, and not accepting enough—it will be all too
easy for the patient to perceive the therapist as a
hostile person, and to have their persecutory
phantasies confirmed.
The missing parts of the whole thing have been
unearthed by analytic writers. For instance, the
reassuring-validating position (maternal vertex) has
been re-discovered by self-psychology analysts,
whereas the dialectic of spontaneity and technical
rigor (O and K vertices) has been explored by
relational analysts. However, the development of a
fully dialectical therapy has been hampered by two
different hurdles. Firstly, although it is widely
recognized by now that pure neutrality cannot exist,
and every analytic relationship is in fact an
interaction, many or most psychoanalysts are still
reluctant to allow for any direct and deliberate
action, if different from the classical "hunting" and
"adversarial" strategies. For instance, one admits
that the analytic relationship can host a "secure
base", but only inasmuch as it is an effect of the
setting, and not of a deliberate reassuring action by
the analyst. Likewise, a certain measure of
spontaneity is tolerated, as long as it is an
unwitting though unavoidable enactment by the analyst,
and not a conscious deviation from the neutral
position.
But how are we to decide if the therapeutic
process requires or does not require reassuring or
spontaneous actions? Is our decision guided by the
process or by the theory? The second and most serious
hurdle to dialectical therapy is the scholastic
defence that makes the therapist theory-responsive
instead of process-responsive. The difference is
that the dialectical therapist does have a theory (or
many theories), but does not depend on it. He or she
uses the theory as long as it is useful, and puts it
aside when it is not. Real therapy, as real life,
cannot be constrained by any theory. Theory is
necessary for a general orientation, or as a point of
departure; but one should always be ready to be
surprised by anything that does not fit in with any
given theory, and consequently to modify it in order
to accommodate the new datum.
One could object that the four-factor model I
am proposing here is a theory like any other, larger
than the two-factor model it is supposed to replace,
and smaller than the six-factor model that sooner or
later will supplant it. I would reply that, firstly,
the four-factor model is dialectical, whereas the
two-factor one is not. This makes a great deal of
difference, because the four-factor model does not
feature just four factors, but more precisely two
couples of factors. It means that the unilaterality of
each factor is compensated by its opposite, with the
result that, for instance, one is not hunted by the
hunt for the truth if one also
experiences the therapeutic relationship as a place
where truth unravels by itself when it is not hunted,
but received.
Secondly, I propose a four-factor model because
it seems to me that virtually all therapeutic
interactions happen within a space defined by two
orthogonal axes connecting these two couples of
factors, but if I now maintained that only my
four-factor model defines the true
dialectical therapy, I would indeed be creating a
theory like those one typically finds in most
psychoanalytic or psychotherapeutic schools. Nothing
is wrong with theories, as long as they are
instrumental in scientific research. Instead much is
wrong, when they become means of identification or
power, as so easily happens in psychoanalytic or
psychotherapeutic schools. Therefore, if somebody
announced that he had found a third axis in the field,
which made it hexagonal, a really
dialectical therapist would be ready to pass from her
four- to the new six-angle field, provided that the
data presented were convincing.
The logic
of the therapeutic relationship is not to be
confused with the four-factor model (or, for that
matter, with any
n-factor model). The four-factor model is just the dialectical
development of the mainstream psychoanalytic
two-factor model, neatly outlined by Friedman. The
logic of the therapeutic relationship is a dialectical
logic, ie one that differs from ordinary logic
inasmuch as it is based on oppositions, whereas the
latter is based on identity. For instance, in the
passage quoted above Friedman defines the adversarial
position (P) as opposed to a reassuring-validating
position (M). This is still inside the logic of
identity (P¹non-P), in which the opposite is considered
only to be excluded. It may be also viewed, however,
as the beginning of a dialectical reasoning, in which
the opposite partakes in the definition of a thing in
an essential way (P=non-M): In a fully unfolded
dialectical logic one thing is what it is only in connection
with what it is not. It means that it is not
enough to say that P is not M—one has to add that P
exists only thanks to M, ie the one cannot go
without the other, either in the family or in the
therapy. This makes explicit the reciprocal
belonging that was implicit in Friedman's formulation.
While in a classic analytical stance the adversarial
factor prevails, and in the self-psychological stance
the validating factor is at the forefront, in a
dialectical approach neither prevails, but the best
synthesis required by the clinical situation at hand
is searched for on a moment-to-moment base. Many
oppositions that lack a dialectical perspective, thus
leading to schisms and to the birth of rival schools,
can be understood in this perspective as different
polarities of the one therapeutic field. References Agazzi, E. (1994). Tra scientismo e scetticismo. In Il mondo incerto, a cura di M. Pera, Bari: Laterza. Benvenuto, S. (1997). La crisi dell'interpretazione. Psicoterapia e scienze umane, 4, 53-78. - - (1999). Eyes wide shut. Is psychoanalysis in touch with the real? Journal of European Psychoanalysis, 8-9, 43-66. Bernardi, E.R. (1989). The role of paradigmatic determinants in psychoanalitic understanding. International. J. of Psychoanalysis., , 70, 2, 341-357. Bion, W.R (1970). Attenzione e interpretazione , Roma: Armando, 1973. Carere-Comes, T. (1999). Beyond Psychotherapy: Dialectical Therapy. J Psychotherapy Integration., 9, 365-396. Contardi, S. (1999). Therapy in psychoanalysis. Journal of European Psychoanalysis, 8-9, 15-20. Fonagy, P. (1999), The process of change and the change of process. Psyche Matters, www.psichematters.com/papers/fonagy.htm Freud, S. (1910). Analisi selvaggia. O.S.F., 6. Torino: Boringhieri. - - (1912). Consigli al medico nel trattamento psicoanalitico. O.S.F., 6. Torino: Boringhieri. Friedman, L. (1997). Ferrum, ignis, and medicina: return to the crucible. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, , 1997, 45, 21-37. Martin Heidegger (1927), Being and time, §32. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962). Hoffman, I.. (1994). Dialectical thinking and therapeutic action in the psychoanalytic process. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 63:187-218. Holt, R. (1962). Individuality and generalization in personality psychology. Journal of Personality, 30, 3, 405-422. Laplanche, J. (1995). La psychoanalyse comme antiherméneutique. Revue des sciences humaines. 13-24. Linehan, M.M. (1993). Cognitive-behavioral
treatment of borderline personality disorder.
New York: Guilford Press. Longhin, L., Mancia, M. (1998). Metodo e verifiche in psicoanalisi: una riflessione epistemologica. In Temi e problemi in psicoanalisi, a c. di Longhin e Mancia. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri Miller, J.A. (1996). Il rovescio dell'interpretazione. La psicoanalisi. 19, 120-124. Napolitani, D. (1999). Psychoanalysis has completed the time of its life. Journal of European Psychoanalysis, 8-9, 21-42. Piaget, J. (1959). The language and thought of the child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [1] The terms "maternal" and "paternal" do not imply that the respective modes are exclusive of the mother or the father, as in fact each of them can be exerted by both parental figures, as by anyone, as a therapist, in a nurturing position. These terms are chosen, however, because validation is mainly a maternal role, as confrontation is mainly paternal: a child with a validating father and a confronting mother could have problems in gender identification. |
Design and Hosting by CyberPsych